Adina Moshavi, «Two Types of Argumentation Involving Rhetorical Questions in Biblical Hebrew Dialogue», Vol. 90 (2009) 32-46
Rhetorical questions (henceforth RQs) often express a premise in a logical argument. Although the use of RQs in arguments has been widely noted, the modes of reasoning underlying the arguments have not received sufficient attention. The present study investigates argumentative RQs in the prose dialogue in Genesis through Kings in the light of pragmatic argumentation theory. Two logical forms, modus tollens and denying the antecedent, are identified as accounting for the majority of arguments expressed by RQs. The first type is generally intended to deductively establish its conclusion, while the second, formally invalid form is used presumptively to challenge the addressee to justify his position. There is also a presumptive variety of the modus tollens argument, which is based on a subjective premise. Both modus tollens and denying the antecedent have similar linguistic representations and can be effective means of refusing directives.
Two Types of Argumentation Involving Rhetorical Questions 43
Denying the antecedent is partially similar to modus tollens, having the
same second premise and conclusion. Only the first premise differs, with “If
B then A†replacing the premise “If A then B.†This simple change converts
the argument to a logically invalid form: if whenever B is true A is true, it
does not follow that A is false simply because B is false.
Although it is not valid, denying the antecedent can be an effective
strategy in rebutting an argument previously made by the addressee: “the
antecedent is denied in an attempt to establish that the consequent [i.e., A] is
not acceptable on the grounds expressed by the conditional premise†(49). In
other words, although denying the antecedent cannot deductively prove that
A is false, it can succeed in shifting the burden of proof for A from the
speaker to the addressee. By showing that A cannot be justified on the basis
of B, the speaker challenges the addressee to put forth a different
justification of A. If he cannot, the speaker argues, he should abandon A.
Samson’s parents’ argument is most plausibly reconstructed as denying
the antecedent:
Premise 1: If there were no wives to be found among your own
people, then you would be justified in going to take a
Philistine woman.
Premise 2: There are wives to be found among your own people.
Conclusion: You should not go to take a Philistine wife.
This works as a presumptive argument against Samson’s apparent belief
that there is nothing wrong with marrying a Philistine woman. The speakers
raise and reject a hypothetical justification for such an action, challenging
Samson to come up with a different rationale. The challenge is strengthened
by the deliberate selection of a patently false proposition B as the subject of
the second premise. By choosing such a proposition, the speaker implicitly
conveys his belief that given any hypothetical proposition B such “If B then
Aâ€, B is false (50). A similar interpretation can be given to the Philistine’s
statement to David in 1 Sam 17,43, another of van Selms’ examples of a
reductio ad absurdum: “Am I a dog, that you come at me with sticks?†The
speaker here implicitly asserts: “If I were a dog, your behavior would be
justifiable. Since that is obviously not the case (nor, I believe, is any other
proposition B that you might offer in justification for your behavior), your
behavior is unjustified.â€
Support for this method of interpretation comes from cases when the
argument contains a pair of RQs, as in the response of the people of Judah
(49) D.M. GODDEN – D. WALTON, “Denying the Antecedent as a Legitimate
Argumentative Strategy: A Dialectical Modelâ€, Informal Logic 24 (2004) 231. BURKE
claims that speakers almost never deny the antecedent, and that arguments that appear to
be of this type are really intended as deductively valid modus ponens or equivalent modus
tollens arguments: M.B. BURKE, “Denying the Antecedent: A Common Fallacyâ€,
Informal Logic 16 (1994) 23-30. For discussion and rebuttal of Burke’s view, see
GODDEN – WALTON, “Denying the Antecedentâ€.
(50) Although the speakers may well believe in addition that there is no conditional
“If B then A†other than the one used in the argument, i.e., that the absence of any
eligible Israelite women is the only justification for marrying a Philistine, this is not
essential to the argument. As shown below, in some arguments it is clear that the speakers
are willing to concede the truth of conditionals aside from those utilized in the argument.